Ðåôåðàò: Adjective
Ðåôåðàò: Adjective
Óíèâåðñèòåò Ðîññèéñêîé àêàäåìèè îáðàçîâàíèÿ
Ðåôåðàò ïî òåîðåòè÷åñêîé ãðàììàòèêå íà òåìó: “Adjective”
Ôàêóëüòåò
èíîñòðàííûõ ÿçûêîâ
311 ãðóïïà
Ìîñêâà, 2001
The adjective expresses the categorial semantics of property of a substance. It
means that each adjective used in tile text presupposes relation to some noun
the property of whose referent it denotes, such as its material, colour,
dimensions, position, state, and other characteristics both permanent and
temporary. It follows from this that, unlike nouns, adjectives do not possess a
full nominative value. Indeed, words like long, hospitable, fragrant
cannot effect any self-dependent nominations; as units of informative sequences
they exist only in collocations showing what is long, who is hospitable, what
is fragrant.
The semantically bound character of the adjective is emphasized in English by
the use of the prop-substitute one in the absence of the notional
head-noun of the phrase. E.g.:
I don't want a yellow balloon, let me have the green one over there.
On the other hand, if the adjective is placed in a nominatively self-dependent
position, this leads to its substantivization. E.g.: Outside it was a
beautiful day, and the sun tinged the snow with red. Cf.: The sun
tinged the snow with the red colour.
Adjectives are distinguished by a specific combinability with nouns, which
they modify, if not accompanied by adjuncts, usually in pre-position, and
occasionally in postposition; by a combinability with link-verbs, both
functional and notional; by a combinability with modifying adverbs.
In the sentence the adjective performs the functions of an attribute and a
predicative. Of the two, the more specific function of the adjective is
that of an attribute, since the function of a predicative can be performed by
the noun as well. There is, though, a profound difference between the
predicative uses of the adjective and the noun which is determined by their
native categorial features. Namely, the predicative adjective expresses some
attributive property of its noun-referent, whereas the predicative noun
expresses various substantival characteristics of its referent, such as its
identification or classification of different types. This can be shown on
examples analysed by definitional and transformational procedures. Cf.:
You talk to people as if they were a group. —> You talk to people as
if they formed a group. Quite obviously, he was a friend. —>
His behaviour was like that of a friend.
Cf., as against the above:
I will be silent as a grave. —> I will be like a silent grave
. Walker felt healthy. —> Walker felt a healthy man. It was
sensational. —> That fact was a sensational fact.
When used as predicatives or post-positional attributes, a considerable number
of adjectives, in addition to the general combinability characteristics of the
whole class, are distinguished by a complementive combinability with nouns. The
complement-expansions of adjectives are effected by means of prepositions.
E.g. fond of, jealous of, curious of, suspicious of; angry with, sick with,
serious about, certain about, happy about; grateful to, thankful to, etc.
Many such adjectival collocations render essentially verbal meanings and some
of them have direct or indirect parallels among verbs. Cf.: be fond of
—love, like; be envious of — envy; be angry with — resent;
be mad for, about - covet; be thankful to — thank.
Alongside of other complementive relations expressed with the help of
prepositions and corresponding to direct and prepositional object-relations of
verbs, some of these adjectives may render relations of addressee. Cf.:
grateful to, indebted to, partial to, useful for.
To the derivational features of adjectives belong a number of suffixes and
prefixes of which the most important are:
-ful (hopeful), -less (flawless),-ish (bluish, -ous
(famous), -ive (decorative), -ic (basic); un-
(unprecedented), in- (inaccurate), pre- (premature).
Among the adjectival affixes should also be named the prefix a-,
constitutive for the stative sub-class which is to be discussed below.
As for the variable (demutative) morphological features, the English
adjective, having lost in the course of the history of English all its forms
of grammatical agreement with the noun, is distinguished only by the hybrid
category of comparison.
All the adjectives are traditionally divided into two large subclasses:
qualitative and relative.
Relative adjectives express such properties of a substance as are
determined by the direct relation of the substance to some other substance.
E.g.: wood — a wooden hut; mathematics — mathematical
precision; history — a historical event;
table — tabular presentation; colour — coloured postcards;
surgery — surgical treatment; the Middle Ages — mediaeval rites.
The nature of this "relationship" in adjectives is best revealed by definitional
correlations. Cf.: a wooden hut — a hut made of wood; a
historical event — an event referring to a certain period of history;
surgical treatment — treatment consisting in the implementation of surgery;
etc.
Qualitative adjectives, as different from relative ones, denote various
qualities of substances which admit of a quantitative estimation, i.e. of
establishing their correlative quantitative measure. The measure of a quality
can be estimated as high or low, adequate or inadequate, sufficient or
insufficient, optimal or excessive. Cf.: an awkward situation
— a very awkward situation; a difficult task — too
difficult a task; an enthusiastic reception — rather an
enthusiastic reception; a hearty welcome — not a very hearty
welcome; etc.
In this connection, the ability of an adjective to form degrees of comparison is
usually taken as a formal sign of its qualitative character, in opposition to a
relative adjective which is understood as incapable of forming degrees of
comparison by definition. Cf.: a pretty girl --a prettier
girl; a quick look — a quicker look; a hearty welcome —
the heartiest of welcomes; a bombastic speech — the most
bombastic speech.
However, in actual speech the described principle of distinction is not at
all strictly observed, which is noted in the very grammar treatises putting
it forward. Two typical cases of contradiction should be pointed out here.
In the first place, substances can possess such qualities as are incompatible
with the idea of degrees of comparison. Accordingly, adjectives denoting these
qualities, while belonging to the qualitative subclass, are in the ordinary
use incapable of forming degrees of comparison. Here refer adjectives like
extinct, immobile, deaf, final, fixed, etc.
In the second place, many adjectives considered under the heading of relative
still can form degrees of comparison, thereby, as it were, transforming the
denoted relative property of a substance into such as can be graded
quantitatively. Cf.: a mediaeval approach—rather a
mediaeval approach — a far more mediaeval approach; of a
military design — of a less military design — of a more
military design;
a grammatical topic ~ a purely grammatical topic — the most
grammatical of the suggested topics.
In order to overcome the demonstrated lack of rigour in the definitions in
question, we may introduce an additional linguistic distinction which is more
adaptable to the chances of usage. The suggested distinction is based on the
evaluative function of adjectives. According as they actually give some
qualitative evaluation to the substance referent or only point out its
corresponding native property, all the adjective functions may be
grammatically divided into "evaluative" and "specificative". In particular,
one and the same adjective, irrespective of its being basically (i.e. in the
sense of the fundamental semantic property of its root constituent)
"relative" or "qualitative", can be used either in the evaluative function
or in the specificative function.
For instance, the adjective good is basically qualitative. On the other
hand, when employed as a grading term in teaching, i.e. a term forming part of
the marking scale together with the grading terms bad, satisfactory,
excellent, it acquires the said specificative value; in other words, it
becomes a specificative, not an evaluative unit in the grammatical sense
(though, dialectically, it does signify in this case a lexical evaluation of the
pupil's progress). Conversely, the adjective wooden is basically relative, but
when used in the broader meaning "expressionless" or "awkward" it acquires an
evaluative force and, consequently, can presuppose a greater or lesser degree
("amount") of the denoted properly in the corresponding referent. E.g.:
Bundle found herself looking into the expressionless, wooden face of
Superintendent Battle (A. Christie). The superintendent was sitting behind a
table and looking more wooden than ever.
The degrees of comparison are essentially evaluative formulas, therefore any
adjective used in a higher comparison degree (comparative, superlative) is
thereby made into an evaluative adjective, if only for the nonce (see the
examples above).
Thus, the introduced distinction between the evaluative and specificative
uses of adjectives, in the long run, emphasizes the fact that the
morphological category of comparison (comparison degrees) is potentially
represented in the whole class of adjectives and is constitutive for it.
Among the words signifying properties of a nounal referent there is a lexemic
set which claims to be recognized as a separate part of speech, i.e. as a class
of words different from the adjectives in its class-forming features. These are
words built up by the prefix a- and denoting different states, mostly
of temporary duration. Here belong lexemes like afraid, agog, adrift,
ablaze. In traditional grammar these words were generally considered under
the heading of "predicative adjectives" (some of them also under the heading
of adverbs), since their most typical position in the sentence is that of a
predicative and they are but occasionally used as pre-positional attributes to
nouns.
Notional words signifying states and specifically used as predicatives were
first identified as a separate part of speech in the Russian language by L. V.
Shcherba and V. V. Vinogradov. The two scholars called the newly identified
part of speech the "category of state" (and, correspondingly, separate words
making up this category, "words of the category of state"). Here belong the
Russian words mostly ending in -o, but also having other suffixes:
òåïëî, çÿáêî, îäèíîêî, ðàäîñòíî, æàëü, ëåíü, etc. Traditionally the Russian
words of the category of state were considered as constituents of (he class of
adverbs, and they are still considered as such by many Russian schiolars.
On the analogy of the Russian "category of state", the English qualifying a-
words of the corresponding meanings were subjected to a lexico-grammatical
analysis and given the part-of-speech heading "category of slate". This
analysis was first conducted by B. A. llyish and later continued by other
linguists. The term "words of the category of state", being rather cumbersome
from the technical point of view, was later changed into "stative words", or
"statives".
The part-of-speech interpretation of the statives is not shared by all
linguists working in the domain of English, and has found both its proponents
and opponents.
Probably the most consistent and explicit exposition of the part-of-speech
interpretation of statives has been given by B. S. Khaimovich and B. I.
Rogovskaya. Their theses supporting the view in question can be summarized as
follows.
First, the statives, called by the quoted authors "adlinks" (by virtue of their
connection with link-verbs and on the analogy of the term "adverbs"), are
allegedly opposed to adjectives on a purely semantic basis, since adjectives
denote "qualities", and statives-adlinks denote "states". Second, as different
from adjectives, statives-adlinks are characterized by the specific prefix
a-. Third, they allegedly do not possess the category of the degrees of
comparison. Fourth, the combinability of statives-adlinks is different from
that of adjectives in so far as they are not used in the pre-positional
attributive function, i.e. are characterized by the absence of the right-hand
combinability with nouns.
The advanced reasons, presupposing many-sided categorial estimation of
statives, are undoubtedly serious and worthy of note. Still, a closer
consideration of the properties of the analysed lexemic set cannot but show
that, on the whole, the said reasons are hardly instrumental in proving the
main idea, i.e. in establishing the English stative as a separate part of
speech. The re-consideration of the stative on the basis of comparison with
the classical adjective inevitably discloses (lie fundamental relationship
between the two, — such relationship as should be interpreted in no other
terms than identity on the part-of-speech level, though, naturally, providing
for their distinct differentiation on the subclass level.
The first scholar who undertook this kind of re-consideration of the lexemic
status of English statives was L. S. Barkhudarov, and in our estimation of
them we essentially follow his principles, pointing out some additional
criteria of argument.
First, considering the basic meaning expressed by the stative, we formulate
it as "stative property", i.e. a kind of property of a nounal referent. As we
already know, the adjective as a whole signifies not "quality" in the narrow
sense, but "property", which is categorially divided into "substantive
quality as such" and "substantive relation". In this respect, statives do not
fundamentally differ from classical adjectives. Moreover, common adjectives
and participles in adjective-type functions can express the same, or, more
specifically, typologically the same properties (or "qualities" in a broader
sense) as are expressed by statives.
Indeed, the main meaning types conveyed by statives are:
the psychic state of a person (afraid, ashamed, aware); the physical
state of a person (astir, afoot); the physical state of an object (
afire, ablaze, aglow); the state of an object in space (askew, awry,
aslant). Meanings of the same order are rendered by pre-positional
adjectives. Cf.:
the living predecessor — the predecessor alive; eager
curiosity — curiosity agog; the burning house — the house
afire; a floating raft — a raft afloat; a half-open door — a
door adjar; slanting ropes — ropes aslant; a
vigilant man — a man awake;
similar cases — cases alike; an excited crowd — a crowd astir.
It goes without saying that many other adjectives and participles convey the
meanings of various states irrespective of their analogy with statives. Cf
. such words of the order of psychic state as despondent, curious, happy,
joyful; such words of the order of human physical state as sound,
refreshed, healthy, hungry; such words of the order of activity state as
busy, functioning, active, employed, etc.
Second, turning to the combinability characteristics of statives, we see that,
though differing from those of the common adjectives in one point negatively,
they basically coincide with them in the other points. As a matter of fact,
statives are not used in attributive pre-position. but, like adjectives, they
are distinguished by the left-hand categorial combinability both with nouns and
link-verbs. Cf.:
The household was nil astir.——The household was all excited — It was
strange to see (the household active at this hour of the day.— It was
strange to see the household active at this hour of the day.
Third, analysing the functions of the stative corresponding to its
combinability patterns, we see that essentially they do not differ from the
functions of the common adjective. Namely, the two basic functions of the
stative are the predicative and the attribute. The similarity of functions
leads to the possibility of the use of a stative and a common adjective in a
homogeneous group. E.g.: Launches and barges moored to the dock were
ablaze and loud with wild sound.
True, the predominant function of the stative, as different from the common
adjective, is that of the predicative. But then, the important structural and
functional peculiarities of statives uniting them in a distinctly separate
set of lexemes cannot be disputed. What is disputed is the status of this set
in relation to the notional parts of speech, not its existence or
identification as such.
Fourth, from our point of view, it would not be quite consistent with the
actual lingual data to place the stative strictly out of the category of
comparison. As we have shown above, the category of comparison is connected
with the functional division of adjectives into evaluative and
specificative, Like common adjectives, statives are subject to this flexible
division, and so in principle they are included into the expression of the
quantitative estimation of the corresponding properties conveyed by them.
True, statives do not take the synthetical forms of the degrees of
comparison, but they are capable of expressing comparison analytically, in
cases where it is to be expressed.
Cf.: Of us all, Jack was the one most aware of the delicate
situation in which we found ourselves. I saw that the adjusting lever stood
far more askew than was allowed by the directions.
Fifth, quantitative considerations, though being a subsidiary factor of
reasoning, tend to support the conjoint part-of-speech interpretation of
statives and common adjectives. Indeed, the total number of statives does not
exceed several dozen (a couple of dozen basic, "stable" units and, probably,
thrice as many "unstable" words of the nature of coinages for the nonce).
This number is negligible in comparison with the number of words of the
otherwise identified notional parts of speech, each of them counting
thousands of units. Why, then, an honour of the part-of-speech status to be
granted to a small group of words not differing in their fundamental lexico-
grammatical features from one of the established large word-classes?
As for the set-forming prefix a-, it hardly deserves a serious
consideration as a formal basis of the part-of-speech identification of
statives simply because formal features cannot be taken in isolation from
functional features. Moreover, as is known, there are words of property not
distinguished by this prefix, which display essential functional
characteristics inherent in the stative set. In particular, here belong such
adjectives as ill, well, glad, sorry, worth (while), subject (to), due
(to), underway, and some others. On the other hand, among the basic
statives we find such as can hardly be analysed into a genuine combination of
the type "prefix + root", because their morphemic parts have become fused into
one indivisible unit in the course of language history, e.g. aware, afraid,
aloof.
Thus, the undertaken semantic and functional analysis shows that statives,
though forming a unified set of words, do not constitute a separate lexemic
class existing in language on exactly the same footing as the noun, the
verb, the adjective, the adverb; rather it should be looked upon as a
subclass within the general class of adjectives. It is essentially an
adjectival subclass, because, due to their peculiar features, statives are
not directly opposed to the notional parts of speech taken together, but are
quite particularly opposed to the rest of adjectives. It means that the
general subcategorization of the class of adjectives should be effected on
the two levels: on the upper level the class will be divided into the
subclass of stative adjectives and common adjectives; on the lower level the
common adjectives fall into qualitative and relative, which division has been
discussed in the foregoing paragraph.
As we see, our final conclusion about the lexico-grammatical nature of
statives appears to have returned them into the lexemic domain in which they
were placed by traditional grammar and from which they were alienated in the
course of subsequent linguistic investigations. A question then arises,
whether these investigations, as well as the discussions accompanying them,
have served any rational purpose at all.
The answer to this question, though, can only be given in the energetic
affirmative. Indeed, all the detailed studies of statives undertaken by quite
a few scholars, all the discussions concerning their systemic location and
other related matters have produced very useful results, both theoretical and
practical.
The traditional view of the stative was not supported by any special
analysis, it was formed on the grounds of mere surface analogies and outer
correlations. The later study of statives resulted in the exposition of their
inner properties, in the discovery of their historical productivity as a
subclass, in their systemic description on the lines of competent inter-
class and inter-level comparisons. And it is due to the undertaken
investigations (which certainly will be continued) that we are now in a
position, though having rejected the fundamental separation of the stative
from the adjective, to name the subclass of statives as one of the peculiar,
idiomatic lexemic features of Modern English.
As is widely known, adjectives display the ability to be easily
substantivized by conversion, i.e. by zero-derivation. Among the noun-
converted adjectives we find both old units, well-established in the system
of lexicon, and also new ones, whose adjectival etymology conveys to the
lexeme the vivid colouring of a new coinage.
For instance, the words a relative or a white or a dear
bear an unquestionable mark of established tradition, while such a noun as a
sensitive used in the following sentence features a distinct flavour of
purposeful conversion: He was a regional man, a man who wrote about
sensitives who live away from the places where things happen.
Compare this with the noun a high in the following example: The weather
report promises a new high in heat and humidity.
From the purely categorial point of view, however, there is no difference
between the adjectives cited in the examples and the ones given in the
foregoing enumeration, since both groups equally express constitutive
categories of the noun, i.e. the number, the case, the gender, the article
determination, and they likewise equally perform normal nounal functions.
On the other hand, among the substantivized adjectives there is a set
characterized by hybrid lexico-grammatical features, as in the following
examples:
The new bill concerning the wage-freeze introduced by the Labour Government
cannot satisfy either the poor, or the rich (Radio Broadcast).
A monster. The word conveyed the ultimate in infamy and debasement
inconceivable to one not native to the times (J. Vance). The train, indulging
all his English nostalgia for the plushy and the genteel, seemed to him
a deceit (M. Bradbury).
The mixed categorial nature of the exemplified words is evident from their
incomplete presentation of the part-of speech characteristics of either nouns
or adjectives. Like nouns, the words are used in the article form; like
nouns, they express the category of number (in a relational way); but their
article and number forms are rigid, being no subject to the regular
structural change inherent in the normal expression of these categories.
Moreover, being categorially unchangeable, the words convey the mixed
adjectival-nounal semantics of property.
The adjectival-nounal words in question are very specific. They are
distinguished by a high productivity and, like statives, are idiomatically
characteristic of Modern English.
On the analogy of verbids these words might be called "adjectivids", since
they are rather nounal forms of adjectives than nouns as such.
The adjectivids fall into two main grammatical subgroups, namely, the subgroup
pluralia tantum {the English, the rich, the unemployed, the uninitiated
, etc.), and the subgroup singularia tantum (the invisible, the
abstract, the tangible, etc.). Semantically, the words of the first
subgroup express sets of people (personal multitudes), while the words of the
second group express abstract ideas of various types and connotations.
The category of adjectival comparison expresses the quantitative
characteristic of the quality of a nounal referent, i.e. it gives a relative
evaluation of the quantity of a quality. The purely relative nature of the
categorial semantics of comparison is reflected in its name.
The category is constituted by the opposition of the three forms known under the
heading of degrees of comparison: the basic form (positive degree),
having no features of corn" parison; the comparative degree form,
having the feature of restricted .superiority (which limits the comparison to
two elements only); the superlative degree form, having the feature of
unrestricted superiority.
It should be noted that the meaning of unrestricted superiority is in-built in
the superlative degree as such, though in practice this form is used in
collocations imposing certain restrictions on the effected comparison; thus,
the form in question may be used to signify restricted superiority, namely, in
cases where a limited number of referents are compared. Cf.: Johnny
was the strongest boy in the company.
As is evident from the example, superiority restriction is shown here not by
the native meaning of the superlative, but by the particular contextual
construction of comparison where the physical strength of one boy is
estimated in relation to that of his companions.
Some linguists approach the number of the degrees of comparison as
problematic on the grounds that the basic form of the adjective does not
express any comparison by itself and therefore should be excluded from the
category. This exclusion would reduce the category to two members only, i.e.
the comparative and superlative degrees.
However, the oppositional interpretation of grammatical categories underlying
our considerations does not admit of such an exclusion; on the contrary, the
non-expression of superiority by the basic form is understood in the
oppositional presentation of comparison as a pre-requisite for the
expression of the category as such. In this expression of the category the
basic form is the unmarked member, not distinguished by any comparison
suffix or comparison auxiliary, while the superiority forms (i.e. the
comparative and superlative) are the marked members, distinguished by the
comparison suffixes or comparison auxiliaries.
That the basic form as the positive degree of comparison does express this
categorial idea, being included in one and the same calegorial series with the
superiority degrees, is clearly shown by its actual uses in comparative
syntactic constructions of equality, as well as comparative syntactic
constructions of negated equality. Cf.: The remark was as bitter
as could be. The Rockies are not so high as the Caucasus.
These constructions are directly correlative with comparative constructions of
inequality built around the comparative and superlative degree forms. Cf
.: That was the bitterest remark I have ever heard from the man. The
Caucasus is higher than the Rockies.
Thus, both formally and semantically, the oppositional basis of the category
of comparison displays a binary nature. In terms of the three degrees of
comparison, on the upper level of presentation the superiority degrees as the
marked member of the opposition are contrasted against the positive degree as
its unmarked member. The superiority degrees, in their turn, form the
opposition of the lower level of presentation, where the comparative degree
features the functionally weak member, and the superlative degree,
respectively, the strong member. The whole of the double oppositional
unity, considered from the semantic angle, constitutes a gradual ternary
opposition.
The synthetical forms of comparison in -er and -(e)st coexist
with the analytical forms of comparison effected by the auxiliaries more
and most. The analytical forms of comparison perform a double function.
On the one hand, they are used with the evaluative adjectives that, due to
their phonemic structure (two-syllable words with the stress on the first
syllable ending in other grapho-phonemic complexes than -er, -y, -le, -ow
or words of more than two-syllable composition) cannot normally take the
synthetical forms of comparison. In this respect, the analytical comparison
forms are in categorial complementary distribution with the synthetical
comparison forms. On the other hand, the analytical forms of comparison, as
different from the synthetical forms, are used to express emphasis, thus
complementing the synthetical forms in the sphere of this important stylistic
connotation. Cf.: The audience became more and more noisy
, and soon the speaker's words were drowned in the general hum of voices.
The structure of the analytical degrees of comparison is meaningfully overt;
these forms are devoid of the feature of "semantic idiomatism" characteristic
of some other categorial analytical forms, such as, for instance, the forms
of the verbal perfect. For this reason the analytical degrees of comparison
invite some linguists to call in question their claim to a categorial status
in English grammar.
In particular, scholars point out the following two factors in support of the
view that the combinations of more/most with the basic form of the
adjective are not the analytical expressions of the morphological category of
comparison, but free syntactic constructions: first, the more/most
-combinations are semantically analogous to combinations of less/least
with the adjective which, in the general opinion, are syntactic combinations of
notional words; second, the most-combination, unlike the synthetic
superlative, can take the indefinite article, expressing not the superlative,
but the elative meaning (i.e. a high, not the highest degree of the respective
quality).
The reasons advanced, though claiming to be based on an analysis of actual
lingual data, can hardly be called convincing as regards their immediate
negative purpose.
Let us first consider the use of the most-combillation with the
indefinite article.
This combination is a common means of expressing elative evaluations of
substance properties. The function of the elative most-construction in
distinction to the function of the superlative most-'construction will
be seen from the following examples:
The speaker launched a most significant personal attack on the Prime
Minister. The most significant of the arguments in a dispute is not
necessarily the most spectacular one.
While the phrase "a most significant (personal) attack" in the first of the two
examples gives the idea of rather a high degree of the quality expressed
irrespective of any directly introduced or implied comparison with other
attacks on the Prime Minister, the phrase "the most significant of the
arguments" expresses exactly the superlative degree of the quality in relation
to the immediately introduced comparison with all the rest of the arguments in
a dispute; the same holds true of the phrase "the most spectacular one". It is
this exclusion of the outwardly superlative adjective from a comparison that
makes it into a simple elative, with its most-constituent turned from
the superlative auxiliary into a kind of a lexical intensifier.
The definite article with the elative most-construction is also
possible, if leaving the elative function less distinctly recognizable (in oral
speech the elative most is commonly left unstressed, the absence of
stress serving as a negative mark of the elative). Cf.: I found myself
in the most awkward situation, for I couldn't give a satisfactory
answer to any question asked by the visitors.
Now, the synthetical superlative degree, as is known, can be used in the
elative function as well, the distinguishing feature of the latter being its
exclusion from a comparison.
Cf.:
Unfortunately, our cooperation with Danny proved the worst experience
for both of us. No doubt Mr. Snider will show you his collection of minerals
with the greatest pleasure.
And this fact gives us a clue for understanding the expressive nature of the
elative superlative as such — the nature that provides it with a permanent
grammatico-stylistic status in the language. Indeed, the expressive
peculiarity of the form consists exactly in the immediate combination of the
two features which outwardly contradict each other:
the categorial form of the superlative on the one hand, and the absence of a
comparison on the other.
That the categorial form of the superlative (i.e. the superlative with its
general functional specification) is essential also for the expression of the
elative semantics can, however paradoxical it might appear, be very well
illustrated by the elative use of the comparative degree. Indeed, the
comparative combination featuring the dative comparative degree is
constructed in such a way as to place it in the functional position of
unrestricted superiority, i.e. in the position specifically characteristic of
the superlative. E.g.:
Nothing gives me greater pleasure than to greet you as our guest of
honour. There is nothing more refreshing than a good swim.
The parallelism of functions between the two forms of comparison (the
comparative degree and the superlative degree) in such and like examples is
unquestionable.
As we see, the elative superlative, though it is not the regular superlative in
the grammatical sense, is still a kind of a specific, grammatically featured
construction. This grammatical specification distinguishes it from common
elative constructions which may be generally defined as syntactic combinations
of an intensely high estimation. E.g.:
an extremely important amendment; a matter of exceeding urgency;
quite an unparalleled beauty; etc.
Thus, from a grammatical point of view, the elative superlative, though
semantically it is "elevated", is nothing else but a degraded superlative,
and its distinct featuring mark with the analytical superlative degree is the
indefinite article: the two forms of the superlative of different functional
purposes receive the two different marks (if not quite rigorously separated
in actual uses) by the article determination treatment.
It follows from the above that the possibility of the most-combination
to be used with the indefinite article cannot in any way be demonstrative of
its non-grammatical character, since the functions of the two superlative
combinations in question, the elative superlative and the genuine superlative,
are different.
Moreover, the use of the indefinite article with the synthetical superlative in
the degraded, dative function is not altogether impossible, though somehow such
a possibility is bluntly denied by certain grammatical manuals. Cf.: He
made a last lame effort to delay the experiment; but Basil was
impervious to suggestion.
But there is one more possibility to formally differentiate the direct and
dative functions of the synthetical superlative, namely, by using the zero
article with the superlative. This latter possibility is noted in some grammar
books (Ganshina, Vasilevskaya, 85). Cf.: Suddenly I was seized with a
sensation of deepest regret.
However, the general tendency of expressing the superlative dative meaning is
by using the analytical form. Incidentally, in the Russian language the
tendency of usage is reverse: it is the synthetical form of the Russian
superlative that is preferred in rendering the dative function. Cf.:
ñëóøàëè ñ æèâåéøèì èíòåðåñîì; ïîâòîðÿëàñü ñêó÷íåéøàÿ èñòîðèÿ;
ïîïàë â ãëóïåéøåå ïîëîæåíèå è ò.ä.
Let us examine now the combinations of less/least with the basic form of
the adjective.
As is well known, the general view of these combinations definitely excludes
them from any connection with categorial analytical forms. Strangely enough,
this rejectionist view of the "negative degrees of comparison" is even taken to
support, not to reject the morphological interpretation of the more/most
-combinations.
The corresponding argument in favour of the rejectionist interpretation consists
in pointing out the functional parallelism existing between the synthetical
degrees of comparison and the more/most-combinations accompanied by
their complementary distribution, if not rigorously pronounced (the different
choice of the forms by different syllabo-phonetical forms of adjectives). The
less/least-combinations, according to this view, are absolutely incompatible
with the synthetical degrees of comparison, since they express not only
different, but opposite meanings.
Now, it does not require a profound analysis to see that, from the
grammatical point of view, the formula "opposite meaning" amounts to
ascertaining the categorial equality of the forms compared. Indeed, if two
forms express the opposite meanings, then they can only belong to units of
the same general order. And we cannot but agree with B. A. Ilyish's thesis
that "there seems to be no sufficient reason for treating the two sets of
phrases in different ways, saying that 'more difficult' is an analytical
form, while 'less difficult' is not" [Ilyish, 60]. True, the cited author
takes this fact rather as demonstration that both types of constructions
should equally be excluded from the domain of analytical forms, but the
problem of the categorial status of the more/most-combinations has been
analysed above.
Thus, the less/least-combinations, similar to the more/most
-combinations, constitute specific forms of comparison, which may be called
forms of "reverse comparison". The two types of forms cannot be syntagmatically
combined in one and the same form of the word, which shows the unity of the
category of comparison. The whole category includes not three, but five
different forms, making up the two series — respectively, direct and reverse.
Of these, the reverse series of comparison (the reverse superiority degrees) is
of far lesser importance than the direct one, which evidently can be explained
by semantic reasons. As a matter of fact, it is more natural to follow the
direct model of comparison based on the principle of addition of qualitative
quantities than on the reverse model of comparison based on the principle of
subtraction of qualitative quantities, since subtraction in general is a far
more abstract process of mental activity than addition. And, probably, exactly
for the same reason the reverse comparatives and superlatives are rivalled in
speech by the corresponding negative syntactic constructions.
Having considered the characteristics of the category of comparison, we can
see more clearly the relation to this category of some usually non-comparable
evaluative adjectives.
Outside the immediate comparative grammatical change of the adjective stand such
evaluative adjectives as contain certain comparative sememic elements in their
semantic structures. In particular, as we have mentioned above, here belong
adjectives that are themselves grading marks of evaluation. Another group of
evaluative non-comparables is formed by adjectives of indefinitely moderated
quality, or, tentatively, "moderating qualifiers", such as whitish, tepid,
half-ironical, semi-detached, etc. But the most peculiar lexemic group of
non-comparables is made up by adjectives expressing the highest degree of a
respective quality, which words can tentatively be called "adjectives of
extreme quality", or "extreme qualifiers", or simply "extremals".
The inherent superlative semantics of extremals is emphasized by the definite
article normally introducing their nounal combinations, exactly similar to the
definite article used with regular collocations of the superlative degree.
Cf.: The ultimate outcome of the talks was encouraging. The
final decision has not yet been made public.
On the other hand, due to the tendency of colloquial speech to contrastive
variation, such extreme qualifiers can sometimes be modified by intensifying
elements. Thus, "the final decision" becomes "a very final decision"; "the
ultimate rejection" turns into "rather an ultimate rejection"; "the crucial
role" is made into "quite a crucial role", etc.
As a result of this kind of modification, the highest grade evaluative force
of these words is not strengthened, but, on the contrary, weakened; the
outwardly extreme qualifiers become degraded extreme qualifiers, even in this
status similar to the regular categorial superlatives degraded in their
elative use.
LITERATURE
1. Ilyish B. “The structure of modern English”, M, 1971
2. Bloch M. “The course in the English grammar”, M, 1983 |